Ari Kandel "Sophocles' Oedipus : Trapped by Taboo" - άρθρο από Columbia Univerity - ΚΟΙΝΩΝΙΚΗ ΣΚΈΨΗ

 




Ari Kandel

Sophocles’ Oedipus : Trapped by Taboo

 

 

 

     "But surely I must fear my mother's bed?"

--Oedipus Tyrannus, line 576

   When Oedipus asks this question of his wife Iocasta, he is unaware of the depth of  his words. The Messenger has just told him about the death of King Polybos of Corinth, Oedipus’ supposed father. Now free in his mind from the threat of Apollo’s prophesy that he would kill his father, Oedipus here wishes to confirm with his wife that, as his supposed mother (the queen of Corinth) is still alive, he must still take care lest he sleep with her, as the oracle also foretold.

   But his words ask a more basic question as well: Why is the prediction that he will sleep with his mother so horribly ominous and repugnant?

  Among all the permissiveness of ancient Greek culture, incest remains a fatally reprehensible offense. Throughout Greek literature, patricide/matricide also seems to be an equally odious crime (see Aeschylus’ Oresteia).

   Oedipus is actually relieved and happy about the natural death of his supposed father Polybos, as in his mind this frees him from the worry that he will someday kill his father. It is these taboos, against incest and against parent murder, that are the main motivations behind the story of Oedipus Tyrannus. Ironically, in the play, these taboos do not prevent moral disintegration as they are intended to do, but directly bring it about.

        The theories presented in Freud’s Totem and Taboo help to explain the motivations behind the attitudes in Oedipus Tyrannus.   Freud holds that all human males innately harbor not a natural aversion to incest, but the opposite: an instinctive sexual attraction to the mother.

  Freud says, “[The experiences of psychoanalysis] have taught . . . that the first sexual impulses of the young are regularly of an incestuous nature” (Totem and Taboo, p. 160).

  Freud also asserts that each male harbors ambivalent feelings towards his father. On one hand, he loves, looks up to, and respects his father. On the other, with the awakening of sexual feelings which initially naturally fix themselves towards the mother, he comes to hate his father as a rival and oppressor.

  Combining these results of his pioneering psychoanalysis and the theory of the “primal horde” based observations of the social structure of the higher apes, Freud suggests an explanation of the source of the taboos against incest and parent murder. At the dawn of humanity, people lived in groups dominated by the most powerful male, the father, who held a sexual monopoly over the group. When each of his sons grew to an age where he would challenge the father's authority in order to get a piece of the action, so to speak, the father drove him away from the group. After several sons had been so treated, they decided to cooperate in order to overthrow the father and get the females, their mothers, for themselves. With their combined strength, they killed the father. However, the hatred they felt towards their father now gave way to their other feelings towards him, and they felt guilt for their actions. They were also faced with the probability of subsequent conflict between each other as each tried to take the murdered father’s place. So, as Freud writes,

 "What the fathers’ presence had formerly prevented they themselves now prohibited in the psychic situation of “subsequent obedience” which we know so well from psychoanalysis. They undid their deed by declaring that the killing of the father ... was not allowed, and renounced the fruits of their deed by denying themselves the liberated [mothers]. Whoever disobeyed became guilty of the two only crimes which troubled primitive society” (Totem &Taboo, p. 185).

 

  Given this origin, as the original two moral laws of humanity, it is no wonder that the taboos against incest and parent murder are felt so deeply by members of subsequent civilizations such as the ancient Greek. By the time of Oedipus, these laws are likely so internalized and natural in human society that a man raised in this society probably experiences them as what feels like an innate aversion to incest and parent murder that usually far overpowers the two desires of Freud’s “Oedipal complex.”

        In Oedipus Tyrannus, these taboos manipulate the characters in strange ways into a plot that temporarily turns Thebes into the seat of a new primal horde. At Oedipus’ birth his parents, terrified by the Delphic oracle’s prophesy that their son will violate the prehistoric taboos on their heads, send him away to die, just as the primal father sent away his sons when he felt threatened by them. The royal family of Corinth then raises Oedipus and inculcates him with all the proper values of Greek society, including of course the internalized taboo against incest and parent slaughter.

   This aversion eventually forces Oedipus to leave Corinth when he finds out about the prophesy. Unbeknownst to him, his fear of violating the taboo actually drives him to break it! Had he not fled Corinth due to his great fear of killing his supposed father and sleeping with his supposed mother, he would likely (the absolute power of the Fates aside) never have met his unknown father King Laius at the crossroads and killed him, nor saved Thebes from the Sphinx and received his mother’s hand in marriage as his reward. Indeed, had King Laius and Queen Iocasta not been so afraid of the implications of the prophecy as to attempt to banish and kill their son, they likely (again, Fate aside!) could have raised him in Thebes as any other prince, imbued him like any other son early on with the taboos against incest and patricide, and lived happily ever after. Oedipus would have known them as his parents, and thus would probably never have dreamed of committing such crimes against them.

   The whole tragedy as it is occurs as a result of Oedipus’ not knowing who his real parents are, not because of any moral shortcoming on Oedipus’ part. However, in the end his actions appear to himself and his fellow citizens more loathsome even than those of any primal brother, as he unwittingly carries the primal brothers’ plan to complete fulfillment, displacing the father and winning the mother. The deep-rootedness of the taboos force him into supreme guilt and make him loathe and torture himself to a greater degree than probably any other character in literature.

   Sophocles seems to have written Oedipus Tyrannus to present the most horrifying tragedies imaginable for any human being. Although he could not possibly have had knowledge of Freud’s psychoanalysis or Darwin’s theories of human evolution, his own insight into the nature of humanity allowed him to figure out mankind’s deepest universal fears an sensibilities. Indeed, his unscientific, artistic insight seems closer to the truth than several of the scientific theories rejected by Freud in Totem and Taboo (see the theories of MacLennan, Westermarck, etc., T&T p. 155-164) which suggest alternate, often biological, causes of the incest taboo. Sophocles’ characters show no innate biological abhorrence of incest and parent slaughter. Only the societal taboos figure in their tragedies. Indeed, Iocasta seems content to live with her and Oedipus' breaking of the taboos when she realizes the truth before Oedipus does. She says, when Oedipus is near to finding out the truth about his background,

 

   “Why ask of whom he spoke? Don’t give it heed; nor try to keep in mind what has been said. It will be wasted labour. I beg you – do not hunt this out – I beg you, if you have any care for your own life.What I am suffering is enough

                                             (Oedipus Tyrannus, lines 1056-62).

 

  Iocasta would prefer that no one ever find out about the crimes that have been committed by Oedipus and her. Although she admits to “suffering” moral pangs, these pangs do not strike deeply enough to unbalance her entire being. What she most fears is the public unveiling of their crimes.

  This is the same guilt that any normal criminal feels when he/she breaks any societal law: some remorse depending on the criminal’s moral fiber, and fear of getting caught! It is not the human creature’s allergi reaction to the violation of an inborn reflex.

   It seems that Sophocles knew, as Freud did, that the taboo against incest does not stem from any innate human instinct, as many have suggested, but from primal laws of human society. Oedipus’ rage and guilt for his actions comes about as a result of both the personal and public realization of his crimes. We may speculate about whether he would have reacted like Iocasta had he been more perceptive and, like her, found out the truth before anyone else.

  The way that Sophocles treats the primal taboos in Oedipus Tyrannus questions their exact nature and validity. Far from preventing discord and strife as they were theoretically intended to do among the primal brothers, their power actually brings about the tragedy in the play.

   Societal standards, including taboos, change alongside culture. Will the taboos that formed the origin of all morality and religion someday outlive their usefulness??? 

 

 

 

πηγή άρθρου: Columbia University

 

 

αναπαραγωγή ανάρτησης

 

 

Λόγος Έμφρων

logosemfron.blogspot.com

[ ανάρτηση 30 Απριλίου 2023 :

Ari Kandel,

Sophocles’ Oedipus: Trapped by Taboo ”,

Columbia University,

Columbia education ]

 

 

 


Karen Margrethe Nielsen "The Tyrant's vice: Pleonexia and Lawlessness in Plato's Republic" - άρθρο - Wiley online Library - Philosophical Perspectives" - ΚΟΙΝΩΝΙΚΗ ΣΚΕΨΗ

 




Karen Margrethe Nielsen

 

[ Η κακία-διαστροφή του τυράννου:

Πλεονεξία και ανομία στην «Πολιτεία» του Πλάτωνος ]

« The Tyrant’s vice:

Pleonexia and Lawlessness

in Plato’s Republic”

 

 

 

 

Karen Margrethe Nielsen,

THE TYRANT'S VICE: PLEONEXIA AND LAWLESSNESS IN PLATO'S REPUBLIC

First published: 12 May 2020

 

  Plato's portrait of the tyrant in book IX of the Republic marks the culmination of Socrates’ defense of the just life. He has been challenged to explain how justice, because of its very self, benefits its possessor and how injustice harms them (367d), and why ‘injustice is the worst thing a soul can have in it’ and ‘justice is the greatest good’ (366e). 

   To explain the effects of justice ‘because of its very self’, Socrates must determine what justice is – its ‘nature and origins’ – and thereby show that we always have reason to prefer the just life over the unjust, regardless of the rewards and reputations that follow from being thought to be just. Since these rewards are ‘simulator accessible’, an unjust person can enjoy them in full, if he ‘creates a façade of illusory virtue’ around himself and ‘deceives those who come near’, while keeping behind the façade ‘the greedy and crafty fox of the wise Archilochus’, as Adeimantus puts it (365c). 

  In this way, the unjust man can reap the rewards of complete injustice while enjoying the benefits of a reputation for perfect justice. He gets the best of both worlds, and can even placate the gods with pleasant prayers and sacrifices: stories of Hades won't stay his hand and deter him from committing the ‘whole of injustice’ (hê holê adikia): kidnapping and enslaving the citizens and installing himself as tyrant (344b-c).

   The defense of the just life is cast as choice: between the life of the perfectly just man with an unearned reputation for the worst injustice, and the life of a perfectly unjust man with an undeserved reputation for perfect justice. To vindicate his claim that ‘justice is the greatest good’, and ‘injustice the worst thing a soul can have in it’, Socrates must show that the tyrant is the least happy of all in the city, although he has committed the whole of injustice and secured the maximum amount of power and wealth for himself.

   What, exactly, is the psychology of vice for Plato? How should we understand the psychological causes of tyranny, the worst form of vice? This question is complicated, not because Plato omits to present a vivid and terrifying portrait of the tyrant in book IX, but because the tyrant by Plato's own lights is not unlike the rest of us, though he lacks fundamental restraints and a sense of shame. In the absence of such restraints, he pursues the aims that we all wish to pursue, but abandon for fear of the consequences. And yet the tyrant pays a price – the highest prince, indeed – for his greed. He is not just wicked, but out of his mind.

    In the most extreme cases, the tyrant becomes a beast, devoid of normative competence: he is incapable of recognizing moral norms, and unable to conform his conduct to moral knowledge. Rather than enjoying the greatest freedom and the purest pleasure, the tyrannical soul ‘is least likely to do what it wants’ (hêkista poiêsei ha an boulêthêi) claims Plato: ‘forcibly driven by the stings of a dronish gadfly (hupo de oistrou aei hekomenê biai)’ the tyrant ‘will be full of disorder and regret (tarachês kai metameleias mestê estai)’ (577e). His soul is ‘full of slavery and unfreedom, with the most decent parts enslaved and with a small, the maddest and most vicious, as their master’ (577d). He has neither friends nor pleasant pastimes to divert him from the consequences of his ruthless pursuit of power. Instead, he lives in a prison of his own making, ‘filled with fears and erotic loves of all kinds’ (579b):

   ‘Even though his soul is really greedy for it, he's the only one in the whole city who can't travel abroad or see the sights that other free people want to see. Instead, he lives like a woman, mostly confined to his own house, and envying any other citizen who happens to travel abroad and see something worthwhile’ (579b).

   ‘A real tyrant is really a slave, compelled to engage in the worst kind of fawning, slavery, and pandering to the worst kind of people. He's so far from satisfying his desires in any way that it is clear – if one happens to know that one must study his whole soul – that he is in the greatest need of most things and truly poor. And, if indeed his state is like that of the city he rules, then, he's full of fear, convulsions, and pains throughout his life’ (579d-e).

   ‘He is inevitably envious, untrustworthy, unjust, friendless, impious, host and nurse to every kind of vice, and […] his ruling makes him even more so. And because of all these, he is extremely unfortunate and goes on to make those near him like himself’ (580a).

  ‘Womanly’, ‘slavish’, ‘fearful’, ‘poor’: the tyrant's ambition has made him the opposite of the manly, masterly, and fearless person he wants to be. While ostensibly the envy of all his subjects – ‘a true man’ (hôs alêthôs anêr, 359b2) – his life is impoverished by his own injustice.

   In this paper, I wish to understand the moral psychology of the tyrant, whether he leads a private life, or ‘some misfortune provides him with the opportunity to become an actual tyrant’ (578c). Why does the tyrant not get what he wants? Why is he enslaved to his own appetites rather than completely free of restraint? How does the tyrant's ‘erotic love’ differ from the appetites of his subjects? When Plato says that the tyrant is ‘forcibly driven by the stings of a dronish gadfly (oistros)’, how should we understand this ‘great winged drone’ (hupopteron kai megan kêphêna, 573a1) and the painful sting it inflicts on the tyrant's soul?

 

«Γοργίας»: το παράδοξο της τυραννίας

   The paradoxes of tyranny are also explored in the Gorgias. Socrates here startles Polus by claiming that ‘orators and tyrants have the least power in the city’, and that ‘they do just about nothing they want to do (ouden gar poiein hôn boulontai hôs epos eipein), though they certainly do whatever they see most fit to do (poiein mentoi hoti an autois doxêi beltiston einai)’ (466d-e). Despite Polus's fawning admiration for Callicles and other powerful men, his life will be frustrated if he follows in their path. 

  Polus (Πώλος) appeals to the tyrant Archelaus (Αρχέλαος) to show that the unjust man is happy, provided he gets away with the ‘whole of injustice’, in Thrasymachus’ words from Republic. I.

  Archelaus (Αρχέλαος) was the illegitimate son of the Macedonian's king's brother by his slave, and so by law himself a slave, but in defiance of his conventional status, he killed the legitimate heirs to the Macedonian throne and installed himself as ruler. It is precisely because he has committed the whole of injustice that he is now the happiest of all, claims Polus.

   If we believe Glaucon's (Γλαύκων) argument concerning Gyges’ ring [το δαχτυλίδι του Γύγη] (Republic II 359c-360d), we would all want to follow Archelaus down the path of injustice if we only could. But because we are too weak to commit injustice with impunity, we create laws and enter into covenants that prevent us from committing injustice in exchange for protection against others’ overreaching. What light can the Gorgias throw on Plato's analysis of the tyrant's wretched life in the Republic and the psychology of vice?

   Readers have paid insufficient attention to Plato's description of the tyrant as lawless (paranomosRepublic. VII 539a cf. IX), and have portrayed him as an extreme kind of intemperate man (akolastos), rather than as the embodiment of the worst kind of injustice. While the tyrant's vice manifests itself though his unrestrained pursuit of pleasure, it is caused by his lawless conception of the good.

  The tyrant does not simply lack temperance (sôphrosunê), as this virtue is described in book IV: ‘unanimity between the naturally better and worse parts of the city and soul that the part with reason should rule, yielding desires that are simple, measured, and in accordance with reason and correct belief’ (431b-432a). The tyrant embodies the worst kind of injustice (adikia), and so he suffers the worst kind of psychological disorder.

 

II

  Vice for Plato (is a character trait that comes in multiple varieties, each kind representing a falling away from the harmonious ordering that characterizes the just man and the just state. This corruption – which culminates in tyranny – has internal psychological causes, as well as external social enabling conditions, in the form of household and state dysfunction.

  The tyrant's vice is the ultimate expression of human nature unchecked by law, whether in its external manifestation in the constitution, or its internal manifestations in the soul. These psychological tendencies exist independently of the political circumstances that allow the tyrannical man to ascend to power as a self-appointed champion of the poor. Indeed, Plato maintains that lawless desires are not restricted to tyrants: they are present in everyone.

   At the start of book IX, Plato observes that ‘some of our unnecessary pleasures and desires are lawless (tôn mê anankaiôn hêdonôn te kai epithumiôn dokousi tines moi einai paranomoi)’ (571b4-5). He acknowledges that ‘they are probably present in everyone, but they are held in check by the laws and the better desires in alliance with reason’ (571b5-7). In a few, godlike people, lawless desires have been eliminated entirely (b7-9), while in others, only a few weak ones remain. The former are presumably the incorruptible people that Glaucon has in mind in book II, when he qualifies his earlier claim that no one is willingly just ‘apart from someone of a godlike character who is disgusted by injustice or one who has gained knowledge and avoids injustice for that reason’ (366c). But such people are few and far between: they are either divine or philosopher kings. And so most people – even the best – will have some lawless desires latent in their souls. These desires are awakened in sleep, when the rest of the soul – the rational, gentle, and ruling part – slumbers. Then the ‘beastly and savage part, full of food and drink, casts off sleep, and seeks to find a way to gratify itself’. At such a time, ‘there is nothing that it dares not do – free of all control by shame or reason’ (571c). The appetitive part doesn't shrink from having sex with anyone, whether man, god, or beast – or even a mother. It is wholly without restraint, both in the object of its pursuit and in its choice of means.

  The only thing that stands between us and the tyrant is the wakefulness of reason and the restrictions imposed by law. That is why someone who wishes to be healthy and moderate should exercise proper sleep hygiene. Before he goes to bed, he should ‘rouse his rational part and feast it on fine arguments and speculations’. He should neither starve nor feast his appetites, so they remain quiet and won't disturb reason with their pleasures and pains. He should soothe the spirited part in the same way, for instance by not turning in while angry. Appetite and spirit need to be quieted and reason roused – that's the only way to ensure that our dreams aren't lawless and that the soul sees the truth in its dreams. For the tyrant, there is no respite. He becomes while awake what he used to become occasionally while asleep (574e). This happens when idlers in the household chase out any remnant of his father's thrift, and the drone they have implanted in his soul – his lazy desire for pleasure – acquires a sting:

‘When the other desires – filled with incense, myrrh, wreaths, wine, and the other pleasures found in their company – buzz about (bombousai) the drone (kêphên) [the leader of the soul], nurturing it and making it grow as large as possible, they plant the seed of longing in it. Then this leader of the soul (ho prostatês tês psuchês) adopts madness as its bodyguard and becomes frenzied. If it finds any beliefs or desires in the man that are thought to be good or that still have some shame, it destroys them and throws them out, until it's purged him of moderation (heôs an kathêrêi sôphrosunês) and filled him with imported madness (mania)’ (Rep. IX 573a-b)

   The drone is a ‘leader of the soul’ – it is put in position of ruler by the swarm of appetites and in turn whips the appetites up into a frenzy, much as a leader of a democratic mob stirs the crowd into action. The use of ‘prostatês’ suggests that the drone represents the leading part of the soul – reason – when it adopts indiscriminate and maximal satisfaction of appetitive desires as its principle. Any desire and any belief that opposes the supremacy of this principle is destroyed and expelled. In the absence of any true belief, madness, in the sense of the deepest illusion about the good – protects the rule of the drone.

   Once the traditional opinions that he has held from childhood about what is fine or shameful have been purged from the tyrant's soul, the lawless desires in the appetitive part are free to seek enjoyment indiscriminately. The tyrannical son uses deceit and force to acquire wealth from any source, lest he suffer greatly from the pain of unfilled cravings. Observing the young tyrant, Plato notes that ‘just as the pleasures that are latecomers outdo (pleon eichon) the older ones and steal away their satisfactions, won't the man himself think that he deserves to outdo (pleon eichein) his father and mother, even though he is younger than they are – to take and spend his father's wealth when he has spent his own share?’ (Rep IX 574a). If they won't give it to him, he will steal it by deceitful means, and if that doesn't work, he will seize it by force.

   How do these ‘lawless’ desires relate to what Glaucon in book II posited as the basic inclination of mankind, namely pleonexia? In book II, Glaucon, playing devil's advocate, sought to prove that no one does justice willingly, but only because they are too weak to do injustice with impunity. Justice is like bad tasting medicine: we only obey the law because we lack the power to do injustice without paying the penalty.

   Glaucon (Γλαύκων) says that we will see this most clearly if we grant a just and an unjust person the freedom to do whatever they like. We can then follow both of them and see where their desires will lead: we will catch the just person red-handed, travelling down the same road as the unjust. The reason for this, says Glaucon, is

  ‘The desire to outdo others and get more and more (pleonexia). That's what everyone's nature naturally pursues as good, but nature is forced by law into the perversion of treating fairness with respect’ (Rep. II 359c)

   Pleonexia is not simply greed, if by ‘greed’ we mean acquisitiveness. It is a kind of greed that does not just want to maximize the good for itself, but to do so at others' expense, in defiance of fairness. It thus arises in matter of distribution, where proportionate equality is at stake. That is why ‘the desire to outdo others and get more and more’ is an apt explication of the Greek term.

  The thought that the desire to get more and more and to outdo others is fundamental to human psychology may seem to paint a bleak picture of humanity. On this conception, a man is by nature a wolf to another man (homo homini lupus est). It is a conception that is rooted in Greek notion of justice as ‘benefiting one's friends and harming one's enemies’ (Republic I 332a) with the only exception being that to the pleonectic man, there are no true friends, only real or potential enemies. If this is right, we are by nature not just greedy, but competitive. We don't just want to ‘get more and more’, but we also want to outdo others. That is, we desire have more than our fair share of divisible benefits while shirking our fair share of burdens. Thus, we all struggle to get to the top, and seek the maximum satisfaction of desires that have been maximized. Interestingly,

   Plato nowhere challenges Glaucon's assumption about human pleonexia, but rather takes it for granted that this is, as it were, the default psychology of humankind in the absence of law. While perfectly rational philosophers will have tamed the beast within, it is still lurking in their souls, otherwise the proscription of private property would be unnecessary: philosophers would be completely immune to the charms of Gyges’ ring. As it is, Plato thinks that ‘our dreams make it clear that there is a dangerous, wild, and lawless form of desire in everyone (deinon ti kai agrion kai anomon epithumiôn eidos hekastôi enesti), even in those of us who seem to be entirely moderate and measured’ (IX 572b).

 

III

   If Glaucon's analysis of human nature is right, we are all driven by the desire to outdo others and get more and more. This does not mean that our desires are inflamed of necessity: in a city that is well governed, we will only pursue pleasures that are beneficial, and not those that are harmful. But this requires restraint and moderation, and does not come naturally.

  In book VIII, Socrates clarifies a distinction that surfaced already on the foundation of the ‘healthy’ and ‘fevered’ cities in book II between necessary and non-necessary desires and pleasures. Those appetites we (1) can't desist from and (2) whose satisfaction benefit us are necessary, since we are ‘by nature compelled to satisfy them’ (558d). Those we could get rid of if we practiced from youth are non-necessary provided that their presence leads to no good or the opposite.

   The desire to eat to the point of health and well-being is natural and necessary. Bread, for instance, is natural and necessary on both counts: it's beneficial, and unless the desire for bread is satisfied, we die. Delicacies are necessary, to the extent that enjoying them is beneficial and promotes our wellbeing. The denizens of the city of pigs do not lead a joyless life, but enjoy measured pleasures. As Socrates describes them, they ‘put their honest cakes and loaves on reeds or clean leaves, and, reclining on beds strewn with yew and myrtle, they feast with their children, drink their wine, and crowned with wreaths, hymn the gods. They enjoy sex with one another but bear no more children than their resources allow, lest they fall into either poverty or war’ (372b-c). This lifestyle is sustainable, and does not lead to disease or competition for resources. It is also utterly unrealistic for people like us.

  Our inborn pleonexia makes us seek pleasures that harm both the body and reason and moderation of the soul. Thus, the cravings of actual people are for non-necessary pleasures. In the city with a fever, the citizens do not live in peace and good health, for they indulge their desire for ‘all sorts of delicacies, perfumed oils, incense, prostitutes and pastries’. Their enjoyment of prostitutes and pastries, together with a newfound love of meat, create a greater need for doctors than before, and so the city with a fever fills up with a class of professional citizens catering to the needs of the fevered population: beauticians, poets, choral dancers, chefs, cooks and swineherds. To finance their indulgence, the citizens ‘surrender themselves to the endless acquisition of money’ and ‘overstep the limit of their necessities’ (373d). The appetitive desires that lead to the pursuit of such luxuries are highly specific versions of natural desires for food, sex and drink: Syracusean cuisine, Sicilian-style dishes, and Corinthian girlfriends, to name a few of the delights that Socrates proscribes for trainee guardians (Republic. III 404d). Such non-necessary desires could be restrained without hurting our chances of leading a healthy and fulfilled life. Indeed, we would be better off without them.

   In book IX, Plato further subdivides the non-necessary desires into lawful and lawless.

  Lawless desires are not just desires for things that threaten the health of our body and the moderation of our soul, but specifically for things that are shameful in themselves insofar as they break fundamental norms and conventions. Though Plato does not offer a firm criterion for when a desire counts as lawless, his examples are evocative, and suggest that lawless desires are desires for incest, cannibalism, murder, and other proscribed activities. Sleeping with one's mother, or seeking satisfaction with anyone else at all, whether man, beast or god, is lawless, as is foul murder and consumption of forbidden food and drink – like human flesh or blood.

   Such desires are the ones that Aristotle classify as beastly in EN VII 5 – not because they cannot be resisted – Aristotle envisions that some beastly characters, like the tyrant Phalaris of Acragas [o τύραννος Φάλαρις του Ακράγαντα], could restrain his desire to eat a child or for some unnatural sexual pleasure (EN VII 5, 1149a14-16) – but because these desires are unnatural in addition to being non-necessary. We do not have to agree with Aristotle's exact list of unnatural behaviors to understand the underlying thought – he throws sex between males in with cannibalism and trichotillomania – nor do we have to agree with his criterion for calling a state or condition bestial. It is still possible to discern a general principle underlying his categorization. In each case, the desire in question is one that arises through disease, bad habits, or congenital conditions that run counter to the norms of nature, as Aristotle perceives them. 

  Lawless desires as Plato describes them break apart social bonds and creates enmity and strife in the city by making the citizens pursue satisfaction indiscriminately and in defiance of norms. But unlike Aristotle, Plato takes such paranomic desires to be part of normal human psychology. Lawless non-necessary pleasures aren't simply excessive, since deriving excessive or highly refined pleasure from food, sex or drink still involves objects that are natural for human beings. They are rather derived from acts or objects that are shameful and lawless in themselves. There's no such thing as sleeping with your mother at the right time, in the right way, for the right result, to paraphrase Aristotle. In each case, pursuing lawless pleasures means transgressing natural boundaries. If we believe Plato, that's an impulse that lurks deep in the souls even of law-abiding citizens.

   How does the greed displayed by the denizens of the fevered city turn into the lawless desires of the tyrant? To answer this question, we need to understand how indulging our limitless desire for unnecessary pleasures unleashes a tyrannical pursuit of lawless and unnatural pleasures. The ‘limitless’ nature of non-necessary desires suggests that they cannot be satisfied. Indeed, on Callicles’ [Καλλικλής] conception of the appetites, satisfaction of all desires would put an end to enjoyment, and so the tyrant will cultivate desires, allowing his appetites to grow as large and numerous as possible while ensuring that he has the power to satisfy them (Gorgias 491e). This is the best life, according to Callicles. Whenever one desire has been sated, we ought to want more, and we ought to be constantly looking for greater and more extreme sources of enjoyment. Once released from restraint, appetitive desires are, in a word, restless.

   This restlessness manifests as a search for new and increasingly bizarre sources of pleasure: ones that exceed past sources in intensity and duration. In the case of the emerging tyrant, Plato notes that ‘pleasures that are latecomers outdo the older ones and steal away their satisfactions’ (IX 574a). Those who indulge their non-necessary appetites will quickly adapt, and need new thrills to experience the pleasure they crave, since old sources no longer deliver. It's not just individual people who ‘outdo’ each other, in other words, but also pleasures themselves. Plato thus discerns an internal dynamic that leads us to seek new objects of enjoyment in place of old, and where the pursuit of gratification leads us from necessary and healthy delicacies, to unnecessary ones, and eventually to the pursuit of lawless pleasures. In the absence of rational restraint and a sense of shame, we will start enjoying objects that are neither necessary nor natural for human beings. This suggests that human pleonexia has the potential to take us all the way to the tyrant's lawless life.

   It is instructive at this point to contrast Plato's pleonectic account of human nature with Thomas Hobbes’ account of human desire in the Leviathan. Hobbes ‘puts for the general inclination of all mankind a perpetuall and restlesse desire of Power after power, that ceaseth onely in death’ – where the power of man is ‘his present means, to obtain some future apparent Good’ (ch. X ‘Of Power, Worth, Dignity, Honour, and Worthinesse’, p. 62). While Hobbes clearly learnt a thing or two from Glaucon's account of the nature and origins of justice in Republic II, his analysis of this ‘perpetuall and restlesse desire’ diverges subtly from Plato's analysis of human nature. In Chapter 11 of the first part of the Leviathan (‘On Man’), Hobbes rejects the idea that human desire can ever be satisfied, which certainly seems like an acknowledgement that we are pleonectic. But Hobbes’ explanation for why we seek more and more powers (broadly speaking) differs from Glaucon's:

‘the Felicity of this life, consisteth not in the repose of a mind satisfied. For there is no such Finis ultimus (utmost ayme,) nor Summum Bonum, (greatest Good,) as is spoken of in the Books of the old Morall Philosophers. Nor can a man any more live, whose Desires are at an end, than he, whose Senses and Imaginations are at a stand. Felicity is a continuall progresse of the desire, from one object to another, the attaining of the former, being still but the way to the later. The cause whereof is, That the object of mans desire, is not to enjoy once onely, and for one instant of time; but to assure for ever, the way of his future desire (…) So that I put for the generall inclination of all mankind, a perpetuall and restlesse desire of Power after power, that ceaseth onely in Death. And the cause of this, is not always that a man hopes for a more intensive delight, that he has already attained to; or that he cannot be content with a moderate power: but because he cannot assure the power and means to live well, which he hath present, without the acquisition of more’ (p. 70).

  To Hobbes’ mind, then, human acquisitiveness and ambition is not a sign that we seek to ‘outdo others and get more and more’, as Glaucon posits, but rather an expression of the fear that we shall not have quiet enjoyment of the powers that we already have. In short, we lack assurance for the future. Hobbes thus reads the Republic through a Protestant lens: people in the state of nature reason like Plato's oligarch, hoarding resources as a bulwark against an uncertain future. Had they been assured of future enjoyment, they could have been content with a ‘moderate power’. But since they can't secure the means to live well, their desires will be ‘perpetuall and restlesse’. To Plato's mind, we all seek more and more because we want to do better than our fellow citizens, not because we are afraid we will lose what little we have.

   The competitive aspect of pleonexia and its drive towards preeminence plays a crucial part in the emergence of the tyrant. While his pursuit of appetitive pleasure drives the budding tyrant to burn through his parents' wealth, and while the need for money makes him break the law, the tyrant's lawbreaking is not primarily instrumental. For the tyrant, breaking the law and casting off all norms and conventions that restrain him is a way of asserting his power, and so to rise above everyone else – citizens he considers competitors in the pursuit of power. The tyrant is driven by appetites strengthened by erôs and madness, but unlike his father, the democratic man, he would not be content to have his appetites fully catered for, since that is in principle, if not always in practice, compatible with leaving as much and as good for others. To the tyrant's mind, any restriction on his greed is an affront: a sign that he is not yet supreme. It is only when he is above the law – a rule-maker rather than a rule-taker – that the tyrant will have achieved the complete freedom from restraint that to his tyrannical mind makes him ‘like a God among humans’, not subject to the laws that according to Thrasymachus make the lives of the ruled wretched.

 

IV

   It is helpful at this point to consider the tyrant's genealogy, to see how he differs from his close relatives. The tyrant is fifth generation in a family in decline, each son displaying a character that is inferior to that of his father. These increasingly corrupted characters reflect the shortcomings of earlier generations, as well as the misfortunes suffered by them in the city. They also reflect the social conditions in the city – the presence of strife and enmity, or the presence of a class of corrupting idlers: ‘drones’ as Plato calls them.

   That there are four types of vice is highlighted already at the end of book IV. Having concluded the provisional analysis of justice as inner harmony, Socrates observes that this should occasion an inquiry into ‘how many forms of vice there are’. ‘From the vantage point we've reached in our argument, it seems to me that there is one form of virtue and an unlimited number of forms of vice, four of which are worth mentioning’ (445c). Since ‘it seems likely’ that there are ‘as many types of soul as there are specific forms of political constitutions’ – namely five souls and five constitutions – they must study each in turn, starting with the best.

   The analysis is delayed, however, while Socrates defends his radical proposals for the guardians' education in books V-VII, and only picked up again at the start of book VIII.

  The best constitution is the one ruled by one outstanding person or a group of outstanding people: kingship or aristocracy. If this is the correct form of government, all the others are deficient in some way.

  In descending order, the vicious constitutions and the vicious character states are timocracy and the timocrat, oligarchy and the oligarchic man, democracy and the democratic man, and tyranny and the tyrant.

  The tyrant, who embodies the worst kind of vice, is thus at the end of a sliding scale of depravity. Aristotle echoes Plato's sentiment about the multiplicity of vice and the singularity of virtue. However, Plato differs from Aristotle in thinking of vices as types of constitutions rather than excessive or deficient states flanking the virtuous mean. The reasons are complex, but the fact that the worst kind of vice is concerned with lawless desires suggests that there could be no appropriate way of enjoying them, and so – by Aristotelian standards – no virtuous mean of which tyranny would be the excessive state.

  Plato identifies different psychopathological causes for each of the steps of the descent into tyranny. There may be an unlimited number of forms of vice, but the causes of discrete kinds are still intelligible and amenable to classification. Virtue – in the form of justice – is rule by reason, and vice the corruption of rational rule.

   This corruption of reason starts with the appearance of the timocrat, a lover of physical training and hunting, as well as exploits in war. He is the son of an aristocrat in a city that isn't well governed, and ends up torn between the influence of his father, and the rest of the household, which pulls him away from moderation and virtue. His aristocratic father leads a private life and doesn't fight back when he is insulted, whether in private or in public in the courts. As a result, he is put at a disadvantage. The timocrat's ambitious mother is angered by her husband's diffidence and blames him for it: ‘she tells her son that his father is unmanly, too easy-going, and all the other things that women repeat over and over again in such cases’ (549d). As a result, the timocrat is pulled in contrary directions: ‘His father nourishes the rational part of his soul and makes it grow; the other nourish the spirited and appetitive parts’ (550b). What the timocrat comes to realize is that ‘those in the city who do their own work are called fools and held to be of little account’, and so he starts craving money as a means to self-assertion. Since he is not a bad man by nature, but merely keeps bad company, Plato argues that he settles in the middle, and surrenders the rule of himself to the middle part – the victory-loving and spirited part. He becomes honour loving and proud, and subordinates the search for truth to a spirited pursuit of positions of high office. However, whether we achieve or retain high office depends more on those who confer such honours than those on which they are conferred, and so a fundamentally decent timocrat will eventually ‘crash against the city like a ship against a reef, spilling out all his possessions, even his life’ (553a).

  The oligarch is the timocrat's son. He watches with alarm as his father suffers a reversal of fortune. The mature timocrat sticks to his principles despite public disapproval, placing honour above all else. When his enemies bear false witness against him in court, he ends up put to death or exiled or disenfranchised. The oligarch, at first inclined to follow in his father's footsteps, now sees him lose everything: ‘humbled by poverty, he turns greedily to making money, and, little by little, saving and working, he amasses property’ (553b). The oligarch desires money, not as a means to the satisfaction of his desires, but rather as an insurance policy against the vicissitudes of fortune. He ‘places the appetitive and money-making part on the throne, setting it up as a great king within himself, adorning it with golden tiaras and collars and girding it with Persian swords’ (553c), not because he seeks pleasure from the satisfaction of his appetitive desires, which he seeks to keep minimal and subordinate to the overarching goal of amassing wealth. The oligarchic man is a miser; he wants money for the power and security that it represents when it remains unspent, not for the pleasure it secures when squandered.

   In this regard, the oligarchic man and his son, the democrat, are both governed by their appetites, but in different ways. The oligarch is a fearful man, he makes a profit from everything and hoards it, and keep his ‘dronish appetites’ in check, though they are present in his soul because of his lack of education. He holds his evil appetites in check ‘not by persuading them that it is better not to act on them or taming them with arguments, but by compulsion and fear, trembling for his other possessions’ (554c). Thus, he is not averse to spending other people's money to satisfy his appetite for luxuries, but he will not contribute his own resources, even for fine ends. Consequently, though his better desires generally control the worse, he is not free from internal civil war, for his ‘dronish appetites’ for luxury are reined in by his thrift, not by a conviction that they shouldn't be satisfied. His son, the democratic man, shares his father's view that it is fine to spend other people's money on luxuries, and so, taking his father's lesson to heart, he helps himself to his father's fortune.

  The democratic man is reared in a ‘miserly and uneducated way’ by an oligarchic father. He is torn between his father's frugal principles and the life of debauchery promised by his friends. When he tastes the honey of the ‘drones’ – hedonistic idlers – and associates with people who can provide ‘every variety of multicolored pleasure in every sort of way’ (559d), this turns him from an oligarchic to a democratic orientation. At first, he suffers from internal strife between the oligarchic principles inside him and the unnecessary desires nurtured by his new friends: ‘sometimes, the democratic party yields to the oligarchic, so that some of the young man's appetites are overcome, others are expelled, a kind of shame arises in his soul, and order is restored’ (560a). However, since the ‘citadel of the young man's soul’ – his rational part – is ‘empty of knowledge, fine ways of living, and words of truth’, his appetitive desires soon grow numerous and strong, and return to occupy the citadel of his soul. The democratic man then returns to the ‘lotus eaters’ – or idling ‘drones’ – and lives with them openly. Having persuaded him that measured and orderly expenditure is boorish and mean, the lotus eaters join forces with his many useless desires, and expel the thrifty part of his soul. They ‘return insolence, anarchy extravagance, and shamelessness from exile in a blaze of torch-light, wreathing them in garlands and accompanying them with a vast chorus of followers’ (560e). Revaluing all values, they call insolence good breeding, anarchy freedom, extravagance magnificence, and shamelessness courage, inverting the relationship between virtues and vices that the democratic man inherited from his father.

  When the ‘great tumult within him’ has spent itself, the frenzy of his youth dies down. The democratic man then puts all pleasures on an equal footing, ‘surrendering rule over himself to whichever desire comes along, as if it were chosen by lot. When that one satisfied, he will surrender rule to another, not disdaining any but satisfying them all equally’ (561b). His overarching principle is that all pleasures and equal and must be valued equally – there is no distinction between pleasures belonging to fine an good desires and pleasures belonging to shameful and base desires that could justify pursuing and valuing the former and restraining the latter:

 ‘And so he lives on, yielding day to day to the desire at hand: Sometimes he drinks heavily while listening to the flute; at other times, he drinks only water and is on a diet; sometimes he goes in for physical training; at other times, he is idle and neglects everything; and sometimes he even occupies himself with what he takes to be philosophy. He often engages in politics, leaping up from his seat and saying and doing whatever comes into his mind. If he happens to admire soldiers, he is carried in that direction, if money-makers, in that one. There is neither order nor necessity in his life, but he calls it pleasant, free, and blessedly happy, and he follows it for as long as he lives’ (Republic. VIII, 561c6-d7)

  The democrat thus levels all natural distinctions between his necessary and unnecessary desires, treating them all as equally valuable and worthy of being satisfied. As a result, he becomes a complex and ‘multi-colored’ man, full of all sorts of characters, with no order or necessity. His enjoyment of the philosophical or political life is short lived, a mere simulacrum. True philosophers seek to know the good with their entire being, putting themselves in order and structuring the city into a harmonious whole. They don't treat philosophical puzzles as a pastime. To be a philosopher is to subordinate all desires to the desire to know the truth, so that no desires swim against the philosophical current: ‘...as Plato notes in the stream-analogy in book VI, ‘when someone's desires flow towards learning and everything of that sort’ he is concerned with the pleasures of the soul itself by itself’, and ‘abandons those that come from the body – if indeed he is a true philosopher and not merely a counterfeit one’ (VI 485d). The democratic man contains a multitude of characters, then, not because he at times has the true character of the politician, and at other times the true character of the philosopher, but because he sometimes engages in activities that mimic the serious commitments of each. He treats philosophical discussion as a pleasant diversion, rather than a way of life.

  Each of these three – the timocrat, oligarch, and democrat – are ‘mixed types’, torn between different conceptions of the fine and noble. They are thus not single-minded in their pursuit of honour, money, and non-necessary pleasures, but rather veer between two commitments (the timocrat, the oligarch) or flit all over the place (the democratic man). In this respect, they all differ from the aristocratic man and the tyrant, who show a firm commitment to a single goal and thus display greater unity of purpose than any of the other characters.

 

V

  The tyrant's pursuit of pleasure is led by the great winged drone in his soul: erotic love. The drone acts as a leader of the mob, rousing his appetites and promising that they will achieve satisfaction without restraint under its leadership. If what I have argued is correct, the drone, as a leader in the soul, represents reason's endorsement of the indiscriminate pursuit of gratification. The leader unifies and protects the appetites against the restraint of shame and law, and kills off any beliefs or desires that oppose the indiscriminate pursuit of gratification. These appetites ‘need many things to satisfy them’ (573d): ‘feasts, revelries, luxuries, and girlfriends, and that sort of thing’ (573d), making the tyrant needy. At least initially, he pursues the same kind of pleasures that the democratic man goes in for in youth, and that he also enjoys, intermittently, in old age.

  Plato describes the life of the democratic man as ‘neither slavish nor lawless (oute aneleutheron oute paranomon)’ (572d2). The democrat has a residual sense of shame, and sometimes restricts his appetites for the sake of his health – perhaps he does dry January or commits to not seeing his Corinthian girlfriend for a while, until he gets bored, and seeks new diversions. His son, the tyrant, ends up lacking even the most residual sense of shame when erôs assumes command of his soul.

  There is a long tradition in Greek literature for associating tyrants with luxury and debauchery. It is tempting to think that the tyrant's vice is ultimate an extreme form of intemperance (akolasia), and that the tyrant's reasons for pursuing increasingly bizarre pleasures is the satisfaction that these objects hold out. Thus, he really relishes the taste of human blood and the satisfactions of sex with animals, gods, and parents. This analysis obscures the overarching argument of the Republic, and Plato’s insistence that the tyrant embodies the worst form of injustice. His injustice consists in his unwillingness to recognize any law that restrains his freedom: the very laws that make human society possibly by imposing limits on our exercise of power. The tyrant’s superior stealth and force ensures that he won’t be punished if he violates the norms and principles that ground human societies. He is an outlaw, and establishes his superiority precisely by committing the acts of injustice with impunity.

   This suggest that it is the breaking of the rule rather than what is achieved by breaking the rule that attracts the tyrant. The tyrant doesn't use political power as a means to the satisfaction of his desires, but rather seeks political power as a an expression of his superiority, expressed by his untrammeled pursuit of pleasures that are prohibited by the laws that bind others. He can do whatever he wants with impunity: that's why he is superior to those he rules, the truly simple minded.

  If this is right, Arruzza does not quite capture the etiology of the tyrant's pursuit of gratification when she claims that

‘[t]he tyrant is incapable of governing himself, and hence is a slavish figure, because he is driven by his eroticized appetites rather than by the autonomous judgments of his rational part. His relationship to political power is instrumental to the futile attempt to satisfy his insatiable appetites, as ruling others is taken as the ultimate means to unlimited enjoyment. And precisely for this reason, his subjects are turned into his slaves and instruments of enjoyment’ (Arruzza p. 182–3).

 

[ Cinzia Arruzza, A Wolf in the City: Tyranny and the Tyrant in Plato's Republic (New York: Oxford University Press, 2019).

 See also Annie Larivée, ‘Eros Tyrannos: Alcibiades as the Model of the Tyrant in book IX of the Republic’The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition, vol. 6 (1), (2012), pp. 1-26.

  For Alcibiades’ lawless character, see Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War, VI 15, 3-4. Plutarch's Life of Alcibiades contains observations that conform to Plato's portrait, though it would be a mistake to think that Plato is trying to capture any particular historical figure in his portrait of the tyrant. About the young Alcibiades, Plutarch reports ‘But all this statecraft and eloquence and lofty purpose and cleverness was attended with great luxuriousness of life, with wanton drunkenness and lewdness (peri potous kai erôtas hubrismata), with effeminacy in dress,—he would trail long purple robes through the market place,—and with prodigal expenditures. He would have the decks of his triremes cut away that he might sleep more softly, his bedding being slung on cords rather than spread on the hard planks. He had a golden shield made for himself, bearing no ancestral device, but an Eros armed with a thunderbolt. The reputable men of the city looked on all these things with loathing and indignation, and feared his contemptuous and lawless spirit (paranomia). They thought such conduct as his tyrant-like and monstrous.’ (XVI). As a young man, he is said to have inflicted gratuitous violence on his elders, just for the fun of it: ‘He once gave Hipponicus a blow with his fist — Hipponicus, the father of Callias, a man of great reputation and influence owing to his wealth and family — not that he had any quarrel with him, or was a prey to anger, but simply for the joke of the thing, on a wager with some companions’ (VIII). ]

 

   While it is true that the tyrant cannot make ‘autonomous judgments’, if by this we mean judgments that are responsive to the good, the alternatives are not (a) being driven by one's appetites or (b) being governed by the autonomous judgments of reason. For the tyrant is governed by reason, but his rational part does not do its own work well, by making him know the good. Instead, it adopts indiscriminate and maximal satisfaction as an end. Reason is not simply instrumental in the tyrant: it sets his end. What makes the tyrant's pursuit of pleasure different from the young democrat's is that the tyrant's rational part, represented by the drone, endorses sensuous gratification as an aim, and deliberately removes all residual obstacles in the soul. He is thus governed by corrupted reason: his vice has destroyed any good principle in his soul, and replaced it with Calliclean hedonism. Since the lawless desires were already present in the tyrant's soul, the removal of restraint, and the resulting state of madness, unleashes his paraphilia and murderous desires.

  Erôs and madness are not just names for the tyrant's appetites, but describe the tyrant's unified commitment to his ends. In this regard, Dominic Scott notes, the tyrant's erôs resembles the philosopher's: both have a single-minded and unwavering commitment to their end. It is therefore not the fact that the tyrant is dominated by erôs that makes him wretched: philosophers too have an erotic attraction to truth and knowledge, and love the whole of it, rather than a part. What erôs adds is unity of purpose: the tyrant is now wholly committed to the life of debauchery, and will shy away from nothing in his pursuit of power. Nor does erôs as such have a distinct object. The references to erôs do not introduce a fourth category of desire, but rather highlights a particular way of seeking the objects of desire, whether the desire is rational or appetitive. If, like the tyrant, your dominant desires are appetitive, erôs makes you pursue appetitive end exclusively and with determination. If, like the philosopher, you desire truth and knowledge, erôs will lead you to pursue this aim exclusively and with determination, setting all other concerns aside. This is already hinted at in Plato's description of the true philosopher in book V. Here he teases Glaucon by comparing the lover of wisdom to a lover of boys, and notes:

‘It isn't appropriate for an erotically inclined man to forget that all boys in the boom of youth pique the interest of a lover of boys and arouse him and that all seem worthy of his care and pleasure. Or isn't that the way you people behave to fine and beautiful boys? You praise a snub-nosed one as cute, a hook-nosed one you say is regal, one in between is well-proportioned, dark ones look manly, and pale ones are children of the gods. And as for a honey-colored boy, do you think that this very term is anything but the euphemistic coinage of a lover who found it easy to tolerate sallowness, provided it was accompanied by the bloom of youth?’ (…) (474d3-474e5)

  The observation about Glaucon as a lover of boys generalizes to all lovers: when someone desires something as a lover of it, he desires everything of that kind, not one part of it and not another. That's why a lover of wisdom – the philosopher – doesn't desire one part of wisdom rather than another, but the whole thing. It is possible, however, to be a lover of something without being driven to pursue it by erôsErôs is an obsessive pursuit of the object of your desire. Erôs is a tyrant because it makes you pursue one goal exclusively and obsessively. It seeks omnipotence like a tyrant. But it does not have a distinct object for Plato; rather erôs describes the way in which one pursues an object of desire. Erotic desire is not a category alongside the other types of desire that Plato identifies in the Republic.

   The tyrant thus seeks to have his way. In so doing, he simultaneously defies normal relations of ruler and ruled, attempting to master his own father and mother, in blatant violation of duties of filial piety. Lawlessness manifests in acts that hubristically defy the sacred and social order. Breaking into people's houses and looting temples shows complete disregard for what is his own and what is someone else's, of what we owe each other and what we owe the gods. As Scott puts it, lawless desires involve ‘transgression of boundaries that would tend to destroy the very possibility of human relationships, family, and society, not just destabilize them (cf. 580a3–4)’ (p. 139): They are, he says ‘blind to the sacred as well as to the social, and the tyrant has cut himself off equally from both’ (p. 139).

   This strikes me as a concise description of lawlessness as Plato describes it. But the drive to lawlessness is not just a byproduct of the tyrant's erotic and single-minded pursuit of pleasure. He does not commit acts of incest, cannibalism, murder, and bestiality simply because such acts help him satisfy his non-necessary desires (it's in any case hard to see how bestiality could be instrumental in this way). Nor does he necessarily derive great pleasure from sleeping with his own mother (however lovely, mom is presumably past her prime). The point of these acts is not enjoyment of the object of appetite, but the transgression of law itself. Such acts express his complete defiance of any authority, whether in the form of human or divine laws. The tyrant can tolerate no master and seeks to outdo everyone, and so he cannot be subject to the same laws that bind citizens together in a political community or the laws that govern the relations between father and son or man and god. His defiance of such laws – and the fact that he gets away with it – is what establishes his dominant position, and this defiance is expressed through his complete freedom from any bonds, even the very bonds that make a community possible. The tyrant is therefore defined by his pursuit of lawless pleasures. They express his most deep-seated convictions and his self-conception as a man who is subject to none and master of all. We thus see how the pleonectic drive that Glaucon posited as the basic inclination of mankind back in book II naturally leads us to lawlessness when reason and our sense of shame have been entirely removed. The erotic love that the drones implant unleash forces that were already present in our souls. It gives birth to madness, and this madness is a kind of hubris: wanting to rule over the gods, and recognizing no limit to one's power.

  It would therefore be a mistake to attempt to shame the tyrant by exposing his behavior for what it is. The tyrant asserts his dominance precisely by acting in defiance of moral and legal norms, and when he is called out for his bad behavior, he simply bares his teeth. If justice is ‘high-minded simplicity’, as Thrasymachus says, and injustice more masterly than justice, then breaking the law is really nothing to be ashamed of – provided that you can get away with it. Power – not satisfaction of desires – is the fundamental motive behind the tyrant's vice. In violating the laws – and so in acting lawlessly – he reveals his true nature.

 

 

VI

  I have argued that the tyrant's lawlessness is not a coincidental consequence of his ruthless pursuit of pleasure and luxury, but rather the way in which he asserts his power and unwillingness to be bound by normal laws and conventions. The tyrant is thus opposed to the rule of law, at least as these laws apply to him: he places himself above the law. By committing ‘the whole of injustice’ and installing himself as a ruler with unlimited powers, he demonstrates that he is by nature entitled to the greatest share of divisible goods in the city.

  For the tyrant, fair distribution is relative to worth, but he measures worth in power, expressed through superior stealth and force. His stealth is displayed in acts of dissimulation, when he presents himself as the champion of the poor, as well as in the ruthless plots by which he dispatches his enemies. His force is displayed in acts of gruesome violence that will deter any potential enemy from challenging his rule. The tyrant is thus unjust, not because his appetites are limitless and without restraint (that would make him intemperate by Plato's lights), but because he thinks he ought to have whatever he wants, because he deserves it. His lack of restraint in breaking fundamental norms against murder, incest and cannibalism, is a symptom of his disdain for the prohibitions and inhibitions that restrain the weak. While acts or murder and savagery may be instrumental on some occasions, and while the tyrant may choose them as a means to an end (the ascent to and defense of power), this is not his main reason for engaging in such acts.

   Richard Kraut captures the tyrant's injustice in a note that has reference to Aristotle's account of injustice in the narrow sense, but that seems equally applicable to the mindset of the tyrannical soul in Plato's Republic:

‘When someone exercises the vice of pleonexia, he does so by violating a law or rule that is generally observed in his community. He regards such rules as illegitimate restraints on his behavior. He has no admiration for his fellow law-abiding citizens, but regards them as mere fools and weaklings. The pleasure he takes in getting the better of them derives from his general contemptuousness toward the law and those who respect the law. His injustice is the expression of his sense of superiority towards others, and the pleasure he takes in his act derives not only from gaining some good (money, honor, safety) but from the satisfaction he takes in expressing his contempt for others’

  As Kraut notes, ‘[s]omeone who is unjust in the narrow sense does not regard the suffering of others as a cost [of doing unjust acts], but as part of the appeal of acting unjustly’ (p. 139).

   The tyrant is the quintessentially unjust person, someone who is not simply soft or self-indulgent, but who treats his share of benefits as a measure of his worth. The ethical outlook of the tyrant – whether in word or in deed – is succinctly summed up by Callicles when he contrasts what is just by nature with what is just by law in the Gorgias. It is just by nature, he claims, that the superior should both rule over and have a greater share than his inferiors:

‘The people who institute laws are the weak and the many. So they institute laws and assign praise and blame with themselves and their own advantage in mind. As a way of frightening the more powerful among men, the ones who are capable of having a greater share, out of getting a greater share than they, they say that getting more than one's share is ‘shameful’ and ‘unjust’, and that doing what's unjust is nothing but trying to get more than one's fair share. I think they like getting an equal share, since they are inferior. These are the reasons why trying to get a greater share than most is said to be unjust and shameful by law and why they call it doing what's unjust. But I believe that nature itself reveals that it's a just thing for the better man and the more capable man to have a greater share than the worse man and the less capable man. Nature shows that this is so in many places; both among the other animals and in whole cities and races of men, it shows that this is what justice has been decided to be: that the superior rule the inferior and have a greater share than them. For what sort of justice did Xerxes go by when he campaigned against Greece, or his father when he campaigned against Scythia? Countless other such examples could be mentioned. I believe that these men do these things in accordance with the nature of what is just – yes, by Zeus, in accordance with the law of nature, and presumably not with the one we institute. We mold the best and the most powerful among us, taking them while they are still young, like lion cubs, and with charms and incantations we subdue them into slavery, telling them that one is supposed to get no more than his fair share, and that's what's admirable and just. But surely, if a man who is equal to it arises, he will shake off, tear apart, and escape all of this, he will trample underfoot our documents, our tricks and charms, and all out laws that violate nature. He, the slave, will rise up and be revealed as our master, and here the justice of nature will shine forth (exelampsen to tês phuseôs dikaion)’ (Gorgias 483b-84b).

 

   Contrast this with Hobbes’ conception of natural law in the Leviathan. Hobbes argues that natural law commands the acknowledgement of ‘naturall equalitie’, and so recommends the making of peace among equals:

‘If in this case, at the making of Peace, men require for themselves, that which they would not have to be granted to others, they do contrary to the precedent law, that commandeth the acknowledgement of naturall equalitie, and therefore also against the law of Nature. The observers of this law, are those we call Modest, and the breakers Arrogant Men. The Greeks call the violation of this law πλεονεξία; that is, a desire of more than their share (Hobbes Leviathan Ch. XV of Other Lawes of Nature).

  This, in effect, is the conventional conception of justice defended by Glaucon in book II. If Thrasymachus is right, it is an inherently unstable agreement, since the assumption of natural equality is false, making democracy naturally prone to a descent into tyranny. On this point, at least, he and Plato agree.

 

VII

I started my discussion by observing the paradoxes of tyranny. The tyrannical man is full of disorder and regret, slavery and unfreedom. Plato adds to the list of characteristics the claim that the tyrant is in the greatest need of most things and truly poor, he is ‘inevitably envious, untrustworthy, unjust, friendless, impious, host and nurse to every kind of vice, and […] his ruling makes him even more so. And because of all of these, he is extremely unfortunate and goes on to make those near him like himself’ (580a). The list of characteristics drives home the tyrant's wretched predicament. Why should we think that Plato is right to attribute these characteristics to the tyrant? After all, he seems to be capable of securing the objects of his appetite, however bizarre, and while he may be poor in spirit, he surely makes up for it in wealth. Why, then, is the tyrant full of regret? And though he may make enemies easily, and cannot trust that his allies are friends rather than sycophants, it seems odd to claim that the tyrant is necessarily friendless: he is certainly capable of entertaining a crowd.

  Why friendless? Why full of regrets? And why does the tyrant not get what he wants? The world is at his beck and call. These startling claims are easier to understand when we see the tyrant's true objective, namely to outdo others. Friendship requires reciprocity and equality, two values the tyrant is loath to recognize. He can only succeed if someone else fails, for what he wants is supremacy as a private individual, and what he promotes is his own private interest, which he sees as in competition with the interests of everyone else. By contrast, philosopher rulers are also supreme, but they rule for the sake of the common good, and precisely because they don't aim to advance their own private interests, they can share a common purpose and hence be friends. Thus, even if the tyrant could overcome his paranoid suspicions, and even if his companions could overcome their fear of sudden death, it is structurally impossible for the tyrant to have friends, since that requires seeking the same good as another.

The tyrant's regrets are also a reflection of the internal logic of his desire. It is impossible for the tyrant to attain what he wants, first, because he can never achieve happiness by pursuing ends that are inimical to human wellbeing. His false conception of the good means that he will never get what he wants. Second, his pursuit of increasingly intense and varied pleasures will not result in maximization, for the pleasures slip though his fingers as his mind adapts, and he falls back into neutrality or pain where once there was pleasure. The tyrant regrets his actions, not because he thinks they are foul – he does not – but because they never bring him the satisfaction he craves. That's why he is truly poor and envious of those who seem to fare better. It is not just because his soul is disordered, then, that the tyrant is wretched: the nature of his disease becomes clear when we consider the self-defeating internal logic of unleashing the swarm of pleonectic desires locked up in the human soul. As Plato might have said, best put a lid on it.

 

 

 

Πηγή: Wiley, Philosophical Perspectives, 1999-2023

 

 

αναπαραγωγή ανάρτησης

 

 

Λόγος Έμφρων

logosemfron.blogspot.com

 [ ανάρτηση 30 Απριλίου 2023 :

Karen Margrethe Nielsen,
The Tyrant’s vice:

Pleonexia and Lawlessness

in Plato’s Republic ”,

Wiley Online Library

ΚΟΙΝΩΝΙΚΗ ΣΚΕΨΗ  ]